The End of History (for Physics)?

In a trio of blog posts from 2010 (see here, here, and here), Sean Carroll defends the striking claim that, as far as concerns the basic physical principles that underlie the phenomena of everyday life, physics has been completed.

[T]here’s no question that the human goal of figuring out the basic rules by which the easily observable world works was one that was achieved once and for all in the twentieth century.

That’s right: “once and for all.” If asked for the basic, underlying story about why a table is solid or why the sun shines or what happens when a person flexes a muscle, modern science gives its answers in terms of “the particles of the Standard Model, interacting through electromagnetism, gravity, and the nuclear forces, according to the principles of quantum mechanics and general relativity.” One hundred years ago, explanations by this story (i.e., body of theory) could not be given, because this story did not exist. “But—here’s the important part—one thousand years from now, you will hear precisely that same story.”

I think Carroll is right, and I think the philosophy of structural realism can help to illuminate why. The purpose of what follows is to explain these points.

To begin, it is necessary to be clear about what Carroll is and is not saying. He is certainly not saying that physical theory is complete. For example, we have no quantum theory of gravity. We do not have a unified theory of the forces of nature, which we would like to have. Again, quantum field theory is perturbative and therefore inexact (albeit extremely accurate), which is less than ideal. Furthermore, there are many phenomena that current physical theory cannot adequately explain (or which even contradict it), such as those having to do with dark matter, dark energy, the Higgs potential that induces spontaneous symmetry breaking, matter/antimatter asymmetry, and the fact that quantum field theory predicts an energy for the vacuum of empty space that is 122 orders of magnitude higher than its observed value (amusingly referred to by physicists as the “vacuum catastrophe”). Therefore, theory in fundamental physics is very far from completed, and everybody knows this, including Sean Carroll. Nor is he saying that existing physical law can explain every exotic fact we might wish to explain, such as gravitational lensing or the accelerated expansion of the universe or why there are three and only three generations of fermions. These are facts it will take new theory to explain.

Instead, Carroll emphasizes that he is talking about the phenomena of “everyday life,” by which I think he means to include not only the solidity of tables and the flexing of muscles, but also advanced technology and anything that can make a practical difference in our lives. For instance, he mentions, as a possible exception to his claim, high-temperature superconductivity, for which there is currently no explanation. But his reply isn’t that it’s not part of everyday life, but rather that its eventual explanation will not require new theory: “Nobody thinks we’re going to have to invent new elementary particles or forces to understand high-Tc superconductivity.” This illustrates two important points about his claim. First, he is not saying that all the phenomena of everyday life are in fact understood. We do not fully understand the weather, cancer, photosynthesis, mental phenomena, or economics. But understanding them is not going to require any new fundamental physics. This is the second point: The physics we have now will be adequate to explain all the phenomena of everyday life. (To the extent that it is the role of physics to explain it. Carroll can sound naively reductionistic sometimes, but let us set that aside. I am also setting aside his claim that physics will explain consciousness. On this point, he is not naïve, just wrong in my view, as my post linked earlier would indicate. There are important questions raised here, but they distract from the main argument. Neither of these issues changes the basic truth he is pointing to, which is that “the physics of everyday life is completely understood.”) And the criterion of everyday life is basically: whatever on Earth we can observe without having to construct a billion-dollar particle collider to observe it.

Thus, Carroll’s claim is limited to what he calls the “everyday regime,” which he does not crisply define but which seems to come down basically to events within certain limits of energy, duration, size, acceleration, etc. And his claim is that we know the laws that govern physical events within that regime “once and for all.”

However, he gives little by way of argument for it. His justification seems to be that physicists generally think it is true, although they rarely state it explicitly, and that he can’t think of any counterexamples. But I think we can do a little better than that by appeal to the principles of structural realism.

Structural realism, as I conceive it (and I promise that’s the last time I will link this piece), is an epistemological doctrine. (There are other interpretations, many of them unfortunately quite absurd in my opinion. See here for a review.) It says that all we will ever learn about the world outside our own minds is its structure and dynamics (or—I think equivalently—its topology and causal interactions). The reason is that to learn about anything outside of your mind requires that you causally interact with it, so that what can make no causal difference cannot be known. Thus, any non-relational, purely intrinsic properties of things outside the mind are forever inaccessible to it. Of course, unless one believes the world could consist of relations all the way down, there must be some purely intrinsic properties of things outside the mind; only we will never know what they are. The function of consciousness is to supply from the inside a substitute for what we cannot learn from the outside. Hence, colors, tastes, felt hot and cold, sounds, etc. are the terms in which we perceive the world, but there is no reason to suppose that they really exist in the world. This is the form of structural realism advanced by writers such as Russell, Maxwell, and Blackburn. It is supported by various converging lines of evidence, among which I would particularly mention David Lewis’s approach to defining theoretical terms.

Now, the approach that I just stated is sometimes called the “upward path” to structural realism. It starts from epistemological principles and works from them to conclusions about what we are able to know. It is contrasted with the “downward path,” associated with the history and philosophy of science, which finds that a staunch realism concerning the interpretation of scientific theories must be relaxed to a weaker, “structural” form to achieve adequacy. The locus classicus of this form of structural realism is a well-known paper by John Worrall. I think Carroll’s claim is best understood by means of the downward path to structural realism, so let me say a little bit about it.

Worrall presents structural realism as “the best of both worlds,” the two worlds being realism and anti-realism. Realism, in Worrall’s view, has the virtue of making sense of the success of scientific theories: they are successful because they are true! Heliocentric astronomy succeeded because the earth really does go around the sun, the germ theory of disease succeeded because there are germs, the atomic theory succeeded because there are atoms, etc. The problem with this is that there are, not uncommonly, scientific revolutions in which theories—including quite powerful and empirically successful ones—get replaced by new theories with very different ontologies. An example would be the replacement of Newtonian mechanics by general relativity. It is sometimes said that general relativity subsumes Newtonian mechanics as “a special case,” but this is a misconception. It is true that the equations of Newtonian mechanics can be derived from those of relativity under certain (never realized) limiting conditions. But this neglects the fact that the two theories make radically different claims about the constitution of the world. Newtonian mechanics pictures space as an absolute, infinite, Euclidean container in which objects that have mass instantaneously attract each other at indefinitely large distances, and in which time, size, and mass are constant properties of objects independent of their velocity. Famously, not one part of this long statement is true in relativity theory. Therefore, although the two theories share some of their mathematics, their descriptions of the world are utterly different. Thus, the scientific revolution that ushered in the theory of relativity was not merely an adjustment or updating of Newtonian mechanics, but the wholesale rejection of the Newtonian description of the world and its replacement with a very different description. And if this can happen to so successful a theory as Newtonian mechanics, what theory is safe? And if no theory is safe, where does this leave the argument that the empirical success of a scientific theory gives us the right to infer that its description of the world is true?

Here, Worrall’s insight (for which he credits Poincaré) is that we can distinguish the relational structure of a scientific theory, as embodied in its mathematical laws, for example, from its ontological claims and then note that although the ontology of an old theory may be wholly discarded by the new theory during a scientific revolution, the relational structure is carried over in an approximate way. Most commonly, the survival of the old theory’s relational structure shows in its appearance in “limiting cases” of the new theory. Thus, as already noted, Einstein’s equations reduce to Newton’s in the limit as velocity goes to zero (and other conditions, depending on the version of relativity theory in question). Moreover, of course, the equations of motion in special relativity are derived from the classical (Newtonian) equations by applying the Lorentz transformations (and the equations of general relativity are derived in turn by applying yet more radical transformations). This would seem to imply that Newton’s laws captured something important about the relational structure of motion, which is evident at velocities that are low relative to the speed of light (the context in which they were formulated), and which survives in the newer theory. Thus, Newton might have been wrong about the constitution of the world—that it consists of absolute space and time in which there is gravitational action at a distance and events that are simultaneous for one observer are simultaneous for all observers—but right about an important aspect of its relational structure.

A different example that Worrall gives concerns the history of optics. Light was conceived in the 18th century to consist of particles. This theory accurately accounted for simple cases of reflection and refraction and for the dispersion of light in a prism. But this theory was replaced in the early 19th century by the very different conception of light as waves in a mechanical medium. The new theory generalized the predictions of the reflection and refraction of light dramatically. It was in turn replaced in the mid-19th century by Maxwell’s theory of light as waves in a non-mechanical, ontologically new entity, the electromagnetic field. This theory in turn was replaced in the early 20th century by the theory that light consists of photons—so, we’re back to particles, only particles now that obey wave equations. These are all quite different ontologies of light—different descriptions of what light is—but at each stage, the new theory preserved in at least an approximate way the equations of the old theory. Worrall describes in detail how, for the transition from the mechanical to the electromagnetic wave theories (Fresnel to Maxwell), the reflection and refraction equations were exactly preserved, despite the ontological change.

Thus, according to this form of structural realism, we should not have too much confidence that the ontology that is implied by our best scientific theories will stand the test of time. But that is compatible with having great confidence that the laws of those theories will do so, at least approximately. And note that the notion of approximation here, although left vague, should be understood to include the continued predictive accuracy that the laws enjoyed prior to theory change. Newton’s laws didn’t become less accurate than they ever were after the development of relativity theory, and neither did Fresnel’s after the development of Maxwell’s equations. Scientific progress, although perhaps not ontologically cumulative, does seem to be predictively and structurally cumulative. That is (my view of) structural realism in the philosophy of science.

In this light, it is clear in what way Carroll’s claim that “the laws underlying the physics of everyday life are completely understood” is correct. Quantum field theory, general relativity, and the Standard Model provide predictions of the most basic phenomena to an astonishing level of accuracy. In a commonly cited example, the magnetic moment of the electron (the amount of torque it undergoes in a magnetic field) is predicted by quantum electrodynamics to an accuracy of one part in 106 (Veltman 2018, 261–263). Perhaps more to Carroll’s point, the predictions have been thoroughly tested and found to be accurate in particle accelerators, where conditions such as energy and velocity go far beyond what Carroll regards as “everyday life.” Although the physics community very much yearns to break the Standard Model somehow and thus find “new physics,” I believe nobody at this point thinks that’s going to happen at the levels of energy we have so far been able to employ in experiments. Since these levels already exceed those of everyday life, it is fair to infer that the body of physical law we have arrived at is not going to change for the everyday regime. Ever.

So for physics, is it “the end of history”? Have we shown that there will be no more revolutions? Not according to structural realism. A main point of structural realism in the philosophy of science is that there can still be revolutions with their implied changes of ontology that do not (or not much) affect the status of the laws of previous theories in the regimes in which they are predictively adequate. It is conceivable that the present body of physical law will be swept up into a “Grand Unification” or “Theory of Everything” or, more radically, some entirely new physical theory that changes our conception of the constitution of nature radically. But, if structural realism is right, then such a new theory will very probably leave the laws of quantum mechanics and general relativity largely intact as limiting cases of the new theory, where the “limits” in question occur in the everyday regime.

Is this the right interpretation of Carroll? The following passage might raise doubts:

What there won’t be is some dramatic paradigm shift that says “Oops, sorry about those electrons and protons and neutrons, we found that they don’t really exist. Now it’s zylbots all the way down.” … The view of electrons and protons and neutrons interacting through the Standard Model and gravity will stay with us forever — added to and better understood, but never replaced or drastically modified.

This might seem to deny the possibility of a new theory with radically different ontological implications. But I don’t think that is what Carroll is saying. And the reason is that I don’t think Carroll regards “electrons and protons and neutrons” with much ontological seriousness even today, without the disruption of any dramatic paradigm shift. Particle physics today—and this is definitely Carroll’s own view (see here)—regards particles as “field quanta,” meaning energetic regions of fields (e.g., the electron field, the electromagnetic field, etc.) that show up in observable interactions as particles. In this view, what is truly fundamental are fields, and what they consist of—if they consist of something still more fundamental—is anyone’s guess. In the meantime, fields in quantum field theory are a part of the mathematical formalism of the theory. Carroll’s point, I think, is that the discovery of something more fundamental is not going to change (“drastically modify”) that formalism. If a dramatic paradigm shift leaves quantum field theory with the status of a limiting case that is largely valid in the everyday regime, as structural realism (and Sean Carroll, if I have him right) says it will, then there will still be fields and field quanta, i.e., electrons and protons and neutrons.

Could the bounds of the everyday regime change? I have spoken of the energies in particle accelerators exceeding those of the everyday regime, but couldn’t we eventually reach the point where we utilize such energies on an everyday basis? Yes, it seems conceivable that we could, and, since civilization depends on the exploitation of energy, I hope for the sake of humanity that we do. But I don’t think that would invalidate Carroll’s claim. Clearly, he is talking about “everyday life” as we live it now. Come the day when everyday life extends beyond the realm where current physics is valid, I imagine Carroll will be happy to be “refuted.”

Rather than worry about what everyday life might entail a thousand years in the future, a better way to look at the remarkable achievement Carroll is pointing to is to think about what everyday life has meant for humanity throughout the whole of our existence up until now. The basic laws that underlie the physics of all the phenomena of everyday life—all of it—for the whole of human history, have now been discovered. That is something we have to thank the 20th century for.

10 thoughts on “The End of History (for Physics)?

  1. “any non-relational, purely intrinsic properties of things outside the mind are forever inaccessible to it. … unless one believes the world could consist of relations all the way down, there must be some purely intrinsic properties of things outside the mind; only we will never know what they are.”

    I’m having trouble putting into words what strikes me as wrong about this; it seems to come from a way of thinking about properties that I find alien. But here’s a first pass:

    If there are no purely intrinsic properties, that doesn’t mean all properties are purely relational. It could instead mean — as seems the more natural way, to me — that all properties have both intrinsic and relational aspects. Not different properties, but different aspects of a single property.

    Liked by 2 people

    • Hi Roderick,

      As a general point, I’m inclined to think that if different aspects of a single property are logically separable, then they are separate properties. Any property, I think, already is an aspect of reality, an aspect we isolate on the qualitative dimension, as it were. By “qualitative,” I basically mean able to be simultaneously instanced in more than one place. Thus, red and flat and electric charge are all “qualitative” aspects of reality—they are properties—as opposed to “quantitative” aspects—particulars—which are individuated spatiotemporally.

      As an example, consider color. This was brought up in the comments to my post about structural realism last year, actually. There it was pointed out that color, which might be supposed the paradigm of an intrinsic property, has a relational structure, namely the color space of hue, saturation, and brightness. And so we might say that the intrinsic color qualities and the relational structure are aspects of the single property of color. That’s okay with me, but the fact remains (I would say) that the intrinsic color qualities are logically separable from the relational structure. To focus just on the hues, the hue wheel depends on the arrangement of two pairs of opponent primaries, red–green and blue–yellow, so that all other hues are mixtures of one member of each pair. For example, orange is reddish yellow. And it seems clear that this relational structure could be filled with many other intrinsic properties besides the hues that we experience. Another species might experience hues in the same structure that are very different from the ones we experience; for all we know, this really happens! And it is conceivable that radically different intrinsic properties could fill this same structure and be experienced as “colors.” Therefore, it seems to me that the intrinsic hues should be regarded as purely intrinsic properties independent of their role in the admittedly relational color space.

      From the point of view of structural realism, the question for the proposal that properties have both relational and intrinsic aspects is whether knowing the relational aspect will enable us to identify the intrinsic aspect. If not, then the argument that the purely intrinsic aspects of extra-mental reality are unknowable seems to hold, regardless of whether we call them properties or merely aspects of properties.

      Liked by 1 person

  2. Just addressing the Carrol claims themselves: I don’t understand how one can be sure that there is not physics of everyday life that we are presently oblivious to. I’m thinking of the example of classical chaos theory, which if I’m not mistaken did not begin to be formulated and experimentally explored until the late ’60’s or the 70’s. Phenomena of classical chaos is all around us, but we just took it as not stuff on which physics might say much. I suppose Poincare’s research on theory of stability of gravitational orbits was a beginning into physics comprehension of such classical phenomena, but now such physics is vastly expanded and has provided some explanations, for example, of some neuronal processes in perception. New classical physics like that can result in new inventions in medicine and in extending observational powers that may well become part of everyday life to.

    Also I wonder what is he saying about things we have invented that have become part of everyday life and that depended on high-level physics such as GPS (general relativity) or transistors and photonic crystals (quantum theory). Then too in the latest issue of Science News I was reading how the two main approaches to quantum gravity physics—string theory and loop quantum gravity—both seem to be converging to some sort of picture in which space is the result of something (yet unknown) more basic. The thing is that I wonder what if such character is in the eventual successful theory of quantum gravity and it includes an explanation of why the place of my keyboard and the place of my fingers don’t just separate to opposite sides of the planet, wouldn’t we then be getting new explanation of physics of everyday life from new developments in fundamental physics?

    These questions may well clear up when I get to study more closely your intriguing exploration here, which I shall definitely be doing.

    Like

    • Hi Stephen,

      I think the basic answer to both of the points you raise is the Carroll is talking about the laws “underlying” the phenomena of everyday life. And by that, I think he means the laws that govern the physical stuff that everything is made of. (And by the way, he thinks everything is made of physical stuff. There is no room for ectoplasm, etc., because anything that interacts with anything physical must also be physical, otherwise the conservation laws will be violated.) So, he is taking for granted a reductionist program, and when he speaks of “the laws underlying the physics of everyday life,” he means the laws that govern the basic structure of all matter. This doesn’t have to be the very lowest possible level of reduction. What if quantum fields turn out to be made of “strings” or something? But it should be a level low enough that all everyday phenomena can be explained in terms of it. This is one of the substantive claims he’s making: there aren’t any phenomena above the level we’ve now reached—elementary particles, let’s say—that can’t be explained without going still deeper. To show a need to go deeper, we must leave the everyday regime. Physicists strongly desire to go deeper, but they seem to have learned that they can’t without leaving the everyday regime, for example by building the next generation of particle accelerators. (The current generation seems to be kind of a dud, actually. The only noteworthy discovery made at the LHC is the Higgs boson. Though we should remember that failure to find certain things, such as the hoped-for “supersymmetry” particles, is a kind of progress, too. By the way, do you remember when some people were worried that turning on the LHC would cause a black hole to form and suck the Earth into it and we would all die? Good times.)

      So, something like chaos theory would be new physics, but not the kind Carroll would accept as invalidating his claim. Nor would, say, discovering some fundamentally new principles of brain organization that explain how long term memories are organized and retrieved. Any new science above the basic reductive level he’s talking about (elementary particles) wouldn’t count as “laws underlying the physics of everyday life.” He grants that we have a lot more to figure out at higher levels.

      Likewise, going the other direction, on the happy day when we get a quantum theory of gravity, that might explain certain aspects of the laws of gravity that relativity theory doesn’t explain, but it’s not going to change those laws—he claims—at least as they apply in the everyday regime. He says that our current understanding of, say, gravity may be “added to and better understood, but never replaced or drastically modified.” He himself believes that space is epiphenomenal, by the way; that is, the result of something more basic. But I haven’t read him on the details.

      Like

  3. David,

    I was wondering if you would say that the relations ‘true’ and ‘false’ can be learned without knowing there are some things (objects, passages, situations, characters) we do not know but can come to know. Also, would you say that only a mind that can know ‘true’ and ‘false’ is a conscious mind?

    I still don’t see how we can know, setting aside specific cases we have proven (such as the unprovability of the axiom of choice or the inability to compute the course of a certain chaotic deterministic process, for which we have the dynamical equations, five minutes into the future due to lack of the required number of bits for the computation existing in the whole of the universe) that there must be things outside the mind that cannot be known. I grant that if there were things (intrinsic properties?) that are not in any situations, then they could not be known; being known is one of the situations of a thing. But that is an empty granting, for no such thing as that can be an existent. A counterexample to the generalization that all existents are situated would, even if a merely open, unspecified counterexample, itself be in the situation of being a counterexample.

    I’ve tried to think of examples in mathematics of items that could be called intrinsic properties along your line, but so far nothing. (Which is encouraging, since my working conjecture is that within my metaphysical framework, mathematics is the discipline studying the formalities of situation, relations being subsidiary of situation [belonging-formalities for synthetic mathematics; tooling-formalities for analytic].)

    I want to dig into Carroll’s writings and into structural realism in philosophy of science, but I guess I have to keep them on hold a good while yet, due to other research and composition.

    Liked by 1 person

    • Hi Stephen,

      I’m not sure what you mean by your first question about learning the relations “true” and “false,” but the question is thought-provoking. I presume that one learns the relations true and false when one discovers that not all representations are accurate. Concerning whether consciousness is required, this is going further into speculation than I’m very comfortable with, but I may as well say that I’m inclined to believe that consciousness is indeed required to have any knowledge of the true and the false. At the end of my post last year on consciousness and structural realism, I speculated that perhaps consciousness—and thus the presentation of intrinsic properties—was required to make intentionality possible; intentionality being the power of representation. If that is true, then consciousness would be required in order to have knowledge of the true and the false, since consciousness would be required in order to have representations of any kind, including any knowledge (knowledge being representational).

      There are three things wrapped in mystery, of which science has so far no account to offer: consciousness, intentionality, and reason. The problem of consciousness has now become a big topic, and difficulties with reason have also been long recognized. (By “reason” I mean basically the recognition of logical relations.) For example, think of Kripke’s discussion of rule-following (in Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language) and the large literature that spawned, or Davidson’s argument for the irreducibility of the mental to the physical in “Mental Events,” which is that types of mental states cannot be mapped onto types of physical states because attributions of the former “must be responsible to the background of reasons, beliefs, and intentions of the individual,” and attributions of the latter must not. The space of reasons and the space of causes are irreducibly different, so that “nomological slack between the mental and the physical is essential as long as we conceive of man as a rational animal.” On the other hand, when it comes to intentionality, there seems to be much less recognition of the problem, mainly due to the influence of information-theoretic attempts to solve it, such as those due to Millikan and Dretske. I think these are unworkable, however. See my dissertation for critique of Dretske, and Tyler Burge for a more general discussion.

      It is interesting how tightly connected this trio—consciousness, intentionality, reason—is. I am inclined to think that all three are non-natural. Consciousness is the most fundamental of the three, with intentionality dependent on consciousness and reason dependent on intentionality. However, I have no idea how all this fits into some larger picture. Especially, I should perhaps make clear that I don’t see any of this as part of a spiritual or religious picture. I am personally not a religious person. It’s just that these conclusions are where the arguments seem to lead.

      The argument for the conclusion that there must be things outside the mind that cannot be known is simply that there must be nonrelational (i.e., “intrinsic”) things, because it can’t be all relations, and non-relational things can’t have causal powers. But I assume you know that. One thing I can say is that nonrelational things don’t become relational by entering into relations. I mean, if A is nonrelational, it doesn’t become relational by being next to B, where “next to” is a relation. By calling A “nonrelational,” we mean essentially nonrelational. This doesn’t prevent A from entering into external relations, like being in a situation or being known. (By “essentially relational,” I mean that its character is defined by reference to other things. For example, having an electric charge is defined by reference to behavior in electric and magnetic fields.)

      Like you, I am inclined to look at math as a study of certain formal relations. In fact, given the structural realist view of knowledge, it’s hard to see how it could be otherwise. But this reminds me of Michael Friedman’s view of Kant’s philosophy of mathematics. According to Friedman, Kant thought that a grasp of mathematical truth required intuition (in Kant’s sense of sensuous experience), not just conception. In order to see that a line is the shortest distance between two points, you have to trace it out in imagination. In order to see that 7+5=12, you have to count it out. Pure conceptual analysis won’t do. This is why these truths are synthetic, not analytic. As I understand it, Friedman thinks Kant was right about this, given the logic available to him. With the development of modern logic and mathematics, however, according to Friedman, pure conception will now do the trick. So, today Kant’s argument would fail, but at the time he wrote it was correct. However, what’s interesting to me is that, on Friedman’s account, Kant holds that math is about (and requires) intrinsic nature: the sensuous experience of space and time. But the structural realist view would be: we can distinguish the relational structure of space and time from our sensuous (conscious) experience of it. And what we can know about space and time is only its relational structure. We have no particular reason to believe that space and time are intrinsically the way we experience them.

      Liked by 1 person

      • Thanks for the attention and all the pointers, David.

        Your understanding of Friedman on Kant on mathematics is my understanding of Friedman also. In 1996 Emily Carson completed her dissertation Mathematics, Metaphysics and Intuition in Kant (under Parsons and Goldfarb at Harvard) which argues against Friedman on this. The insolence. I don’t know if you have heard, but Daniel Sutherland’s book, sure to be worthwhile for me, has been issued this year (and is on my shelf): Kant’s Mathematical World – Mathematics, Cognition, and Experience. I’ll be getting to all of those, though probably not until next year, as part of my project of developing a philosophy of mathematics suited tightly to my metaphysics. Sutherland is still at UIC. We took a seminar from Stein at UC back in the day.

        I don’t know if you’ve heard, but Tyler Burge has a new book, to be released later this year, titled Perception: First Form of Mind. I have studied some in his Origins book, and I’ll be adding this one to the shelf and studies as well.

        And returning, as ever, to your dissertation.

        Liked by 1 person

        • Hi Stephen,

          In the spring of 2001, Daniel Sutherland and I organized a conference on “Kant’s Philosophy of Mathematics and Science.” That is—somewhat more honestly—he organized it and I helped. Here is a link to the flyer. Besides Sutherland, Michael Friedman, Emily Carson, and Charles Parsons were all on the program.

          I had not known about the new Tyler Burge book. But it’s now pre-ordered!

          Liked by 1 person

          • Yes, what an absolutely fabulous conference.

            I was there, and I have a paper file from it. Therein I have the program flyer and some handouts all marked up. I remember the thanks they gave to you for making the occasion happen. Beyond Michael’s handout, I evidently asked you to send me a copy of his paper. This you accomplished 29 August 2001.

            Your note attached to the paper includes:
            “I’m sorry it took so long to get this to you (my copier broke down . . . it’s so old we just had to junk it). . . .
            “This term . . . I’m reading Aristotle (Eudemian Ethics – in Greek!) and otherwise trying to concentrate on cognition stuff (which will be my dissertation). Will be a while before I can get back to Kant, I’m afraid. . . .”

            I’ve gathered that humans need each other to get more knowledge, but as well, to restore bits to memory. Glad you mentioned this conference, as it got me to pull that file and promote it to Kant shelves here in the main library.

            Like

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s